|
Rick Garnett
The politics of education reform are a mystery. Millionaire businessmen
and conservative activists invoke civil-rights ideals to demand
equality, freedom, and diversity in education while liberals
join union bosses and anti-religious activists in support of a government
monopoly. Strange days indeed, when the NAACP's and ACLU's opponents
are black schoolchildren singing "We Shall Overcome" on
the courthouse steps.
Enter Joseph Viteritti, whose Choosing Equality is a compelling
cry for meaningful school choice. Viteritti is an education expert
who knows the data and has studied the studies, but Choosing Equality
is not a numbers-crunching book. Indeed, its strength lies in the
fact that it builds the case for school choice not so much on an
economic-efficiency model but on the Constitution's promise of equality.
That promise was most famously affirmed in 1954 when the Supreme
Court declared in Brown v. Board of Education that no child "may
reasonably be expected to succeed in life if he is denied the opportunity
of an education. Such an opportunity . . . is a right that must
be made available to all on equal terms."
Choosing Equality shows that making good on Brown's promise requires
us to empower parents to choose the best education for their children.
Viteritti begins with the simple observation that some Americans
those with enough money already have school choice.
But the education establishment's allegiance to the government's
monopoly on public education "has consigned an entire segment
of the population to schools that most middle-class parents would
not allow their sons and daughters to attend." The self-interest
of teachers' unions, the political calculations of their elected
allies, faulty constitutional reasoning, and a misplaced suspicion
of religious schools have trumped the educational needs and rights
of poor children. "The most compelling argument for school
choice in America," Viteritti insists, "remains an egalitarian
one: Education is such an essential public good for living life
in a free and prosperous society that all people deserve equal access
to its benefits."
Just one year after Brown, the economist Milton Friedman suggested
replacing the government's education monopoly with a universal government-funded
voucher system. Friedman was ahead of his time, but in the years
that followed, many thinkers took up the idea of vouchers. Free-market
economists liked the competition, liberals liked the idea of saving
poor children from bad schools, and cultural and religious minorities
hoped to protect their values and traditions from state-imposed
homogenization.
School choice failed to catch hold in politics, however, in large
part because of the vehement opposition of the teachers' unions
and the increasing identification of school choice with religious
conservatives. As a result, many choice supporters lowered their
sights to more modest reforms, such as intra-district public-school
choice, "magnet" schools, privately managed public schools,
and charter schools. As Choosing Equality shows, these compromises
share the problem of "not enough choice, too much control."
Even charter schools which provide convenient political cover
for politicians who are required by what William Bennett has called
the education-establishment "Blob" to oppose real choice
have fallen short of reformers' hopes. What Viteritti calls
"Potemkin bills that pretend to be serious reforms but lack
the essential ingredients of strong laws" and disingenuous
lawsuits have often succeeded in hamstringing charter schools with
the same regulations that cripple the public schools. "Controlled
choice" doesn't work, but, Viteritti insists, real choice can,
if private and religious schools are included in parents' educational
menu.
In emphasizing the importance of eschewing discrimination against
religious schools, Viteritti follows John Chubb and Terry Moe, who
proposed in 1990 a program through which public, private, and religious
schools would compete for government money. Chubb and Moe transformed
school choice from a topic for dusty policy journals to a national
political issue, and by 1997 the "paradoxical politics of choice"
were at center stage. A liberal president who "defined himself
as a champion of the poor" killed a modest voucher proposal
for poor children in the District of Columbia that the plan's intended
beneficiaries the District's low-income, predominantly black
residents overwhelmingly supported. As Viteritti observes,
President Clinton's uncharacteristic fortitude in opposing choice
"epitomized one of the great dilemmas of liberal Democratic
politics: On the one hand, sympathetic to the plight of the disadvantaged,
concerned with the tragic condition of public education in cities;
on the other hand, deeply indebted to the education establishment
and the powerful teachers' unions."
Even as the president was making the District of Columbia safe
for monopoly, however, a number of local and private initiatives
around the country were serving as "laboratories for experimentation
with an idea whose time had finally come." In Atlanta, at a
ceremony for the forty-thousand students awarded scholarships through
Ted Forstmann and John Walton's Children's Scholarship Fund, former
mayor Andrew Young declared, "In the words of the old Negro
spiritual: Great Day!" In Milwaukee, Polly Williams, a black,
single mother of four, joined hands with Howard Fuller, a community
activist and unlikely superintendent of schools, to beat back the
unions and, eventually, to enact a limited scholarship program for
poor children. And in Cleveland, Fannie Lewis, the indefatigable
councilwoman from Cleveland's low-income, primarily black, Hough
neighborhood, allied with David Brennan, a wealthy Ohio businessman,
to push a program choice through the Ohio legislature.
Notwithstanding black parents' overwhelming support for the scholarship
proposals, however, "public interest" legal organizations
rushed to attack in the courts what they couldn't defeat in the
legislatures. The Wisconsin Supreme Court held that the Milwaukee
program did not violate the First Amendment. But in Cleveland, the
anti-choice interest groups managed to convince a federal judge,
just days before the opening of the school year, to pull thousands
of poor children out of their chosen schools. The judge later reconsidered,
and the Supreme Court stayed his ruling, keeping the Cleveland program
running. But its legal status remains uncertain.
The Milwaukee and Cleveland cases illustrate how church-state jurisprudence
stymies meaningful school reform. "The idea of strict separation
is," as Viteritti puts it, "of recent vintage and, so
far as the Supreme Court is concerned, was short lived." As
late as the 1950s, the Supreme Court was still mostly accomodationalist
in its religion jurisprudence. But the 1970s "ushered in a
ten-year period of judicial decision-making that was confused and
incoherent in its thinking. If there was any rhyme or reason to
the Court's First Amendment jurisprudence, it coalesced around a
separationalist philosophy that was insensitive to the interests
of religious believers and out of touch with a tradition of toleration
that dates back to the first Congress of the United States."
It is this dark decade that provides anti-choice lawyers with their
"arsenal of legal precedent."
Over the last fifteen years, the Supreme Court has done much to
undo the damage, holding in a series of cases that the Constitution
requires neutrality, not hostility, toward religion and religious
schools. Most Court watchers agree that it is only a matter of time
before the Court finally repudiates voucher opponents' favorite
weapon, the 1973 Nyquist case, which struck down a New York program
that provided public assistance to parochial schools.
But there are other obstacles ahead. Choosing Equality's most important
contribution to the legal debate is its discussion of the "common
school" myth that provides so much of the rhetorical ammunition
for the defenders of monopoly and their analysis of the various
state constitutional provisions that grew out of nineteenth-century
nativist movements and forbid aid to religious schools.
Like most choice supporters, Viteritti strongly endorses public
funding of education, but he argues that "there is no episode
in the American chronicle that better illustrates the inherent dangers
of majority rule that so preoccupied Madison than the history of
the common school." It was only in reaction to the waves of
Catholic and Jewish immigrants in the nineteenth century that the
idea of a "common school" system began to catch hold as
a way of Americanizing the newcomers and freeing them from their
native superstitions. "One cannot reasonably separate,"
Viteritti insists, "the founding of the American common school
from the obtrusive nativism that had its origins at the Protestant
pulpit during the early nineteenth century."
The common-school movement was not a civil-society triumph, but
a "telling story of the risks involved when a political majority
is allowed to establish a monopoly."
The common schools' nativist agenda was supplemented with laws
banning government support of parochial schools. Maine congressman
James G. Blaine proposed to correct the "defect" in the
United States Constitution that permitted states to aid parochial
schools, and though the "Blaine Amendment" which
would have done to the Constitution's text what the Supreme Court
later did through interpretation failed, radical Republicans
managed to get "baby Blaine amendments" inserted in the
constitutions of nearly thirty states. This "unholy alliance
between the public-school lobby and nativist political forces would
carry over well into the twentieth century,"and continues even
today when voucher opponents hint darkly about the insidious influence
of the Catholic Church, and some liberal academics emphasize the
public schools' important mission to liberate students "from
the ways of thinking imposed by religions and other traditions of
thought."
Choosing Equality shows that Blaine's legacy and the intransigence
of the education establishment are undermining the ideals demanded
by Brown v. Board of Education. Viteritti has wisely shifted
or at least re-focused the terms of the school-choice debate
from economics to equality, citizenship, and civil society.
In the end, it is not enough to say that religious schools educate
well or that school choice would promote efficiency. The best argument
for school choice, Viteritti shows, is that it is essential to achieving
equality of opportunity for American children, rich or poor. School
choice treats the poor as citizens of equal dignity; it promotes
the independence upon which constitutional government depends; and
it empowers parents to transmit their values to their children.
The advocates of school choice, not the public-education monopoly,
are the people who promise to invigorate public life, create more
capable citizens, bring together the races, and make good on the
Constitution's promises.
NOTE: This article is reprinted with permission of The Weekly Standard,
it first appeared on December 13, 1999. For more information on
subscribing to The Weekly Standard please call 1-800-283-2014 or
visit the website http://www.weeklystandard.com.
|