Joel Edan Friedlander*
The Supreme Court's recent decision in Romer v. Evans1 appears
to have been written with the expectation that it would become an
artifact in our nation's cultural history. Justice Kennedy's majority
opinion begins by quoting the sole dissent in Plessy v. Ferguson2.
"One century ago," Justice Kennedy intones, "the
first Justice Harlan admonished this Court that the Constitution
`neither knows nor tolerates classes among citizens.'" Justice
Harlan's denunciation of state-enforced racial segregation is resurrected
to strike down a state constitutional amendment, Colorado's Amendment
2, which prohibited gays, lesbians and bisexuals from being granted
protected legal status.
Never before has the Supreme Court equated a racial classification
with laws prohibiting or disfavoring a type of sexual conduct. This
fact alone guarantees that Romer will be one of the few cases, such
as Plessy, that will always be required reading, whether or not
it remains good law.
The overturning of Plessy was partly due to the rhetorical strength
of its dissenting opinion. Justice Harlan spoke of a "colorblind"
Constitution, the principle upon which the civil rights movement
was founded. Those who believe that the Court has again committed
a grave error will look for similar sustenance in the dissenting
opinion of Justice Scalia. But instead of reading about the inseparability
of constitutional government and public morality, there they will
smell the hint of self-defeat.
Justice Scalia's dissent is itself historic. Its first sentence
invokes a German word never before found in the U.S. Reports: "The
Court has mistaken a Kulturkampf for a fit of spite." Colorado's
Amendment 2, he explains, was not enacted out of a desire to harm
homosexuals, as the majority had assumed. Instead, the amendment
was the product of what Scalia calls "the culture wars."
In this fight, Colorado had made "a modest attempt . . . to
preserve traditional sexual mores against the efforts of a politically
powerful minority to revise those mores through the use of the laws."
Justice Scalia accurately describes the fight over Amendment 2
as part of a wider Kulturkampf. According to the leading contemporary
theorist of Kulturkampf, the sociologist Philip Rieff, the German
conflation loosely translated as "culture struggle" is
the process by which every culture renews itself and disarms its
competitorsfirst by words, next by law, and finally, if necessary,
by military force.
In Rieffian theory, Kulturkampf is a permanent condition. The history
of the West is the history of warring cultures, originally struggles
among pagan cultures, and then against and among the monotheistic
cultures that originated in Jerusalem. What distinguishes the modern
Kulturkampf is that it is now a struggle against inherited culture
in all its forms. Modern ideological movements aim to disarm the
prohibitions and traditions inherited from classical Judaism and
Christianity, such as the prohibition against homosexuality.
Rieff locates the origins of the modem Kulturkampf in Bismarckian
Germany. He writes that the word Kulturkampf
first appeared in common German use in the early 1870's during
the struggle of the National Liberal political party to disarm by
law the moral / educational authority, and political pulpitry, of
a triumphalist Roman Catholic hierarchy, revitalized as it then
was by its dogma of papal infallibility in matters of faith and
morals. The aim of the National Liberals was to shift the German
Catholic imagination away from the church to the state.3
The present Kulturkampf is a continued attempt to shift the public
imagination away from institutions that impose moral demands, and
toward the secular power of the state.
The Romer opinions reveal that Justices Kennedy and Scalia have
each made their peace with the state in its continuing struggle
against culture. Justice Kennedy sides with the liberal statists
on the Court who seek to disestablish both religion and the moral
convictions of the religious. Justice Scalia's position is different
but no less radical. Having diagnosed the Kulturkampf, he believes
that the Court must refuse "to take sides in this culture war"
because "the Constitution of the United States says nothing
about the subject."
Justice Scalia's neutrality is no affectation. The Romer dissent
embodies his deep commitment to judicial deference. The dissent
is laced with barbed intensity toward the majority, not because
they have taken the wrong side in the Kulturkampf, but because they
have taken sides at all.
Unlike Justice Harlan, who appealed to moral principle in Plessy,
Justice Scalia reasons from logic and legal precedent. Nowhere in
his dissent does he locate the constitutional authority for Amendment
2. Instead, he belittles the majority for their failure to marshal
sufficient authorities. Thus in the first section of his dissent,
Justice Scalia attacks the illogic of the majority opinion, which
he reasons, accurately enough, to be founded on the principle "that
one who is accorded equal protection under the laws, but cannot
as readily as others obtain preferential treatment under the laws,
has been denied equal protection of the laws." This principle
is not only historically unfounded, Scalia writes, it represents
"terminal silliness."
Section two of the dissent inquires whether the prohibition of
special protection for homosexuals has a "legitimate rational
basis." Justice Scalia concludes that it does, based on the
Court's decision ten years ago, in Bowers v. Hardwick4, that homosexual
conduct could be criminalized. Chiding the majority for failing
to mention Bowers, Justice Scalia reasons that if it is constitutional
for a State to make homosexual conduct criminal, the State must
be able to adopt a provision "merely prohibiting all levels
of state government from bestowing special protections upon homosexual
conduct."
These portions of the dissent show how arguments from logic and
precedent can be an effective bulwark against assaults on inherited
culture. But the second half of the dissent reveals the extent to
which Justice Scalia has been rhetorically disarmed by his conception
of the judicial role.
Homosexuals, he writes, are a geographically concentrated and politically
powerful minority who have used their political power to push for
school curricula teaching that "homosexuality is an optional
and fully acceptable `alternate life style,'" and to enact
local ordinances prohibiting discrimination on the basis of sexual
orientation. With this state of affairs Justice Scalia has no quarrel.
"I do not mean to be critical of these legislative successes;
homosexuals are as entitled to use the legal system for reinforcement
of their moral sentiments as are the rest of society."
That extraordinary statement stands unsupported. As Justice Scalia
himself observes, the weight of precedent falls exclusively on the
side of Amendment 2. Justice Scalia finds historical sanction for
Amendment 2 in state constitutional amendments outlawing polygamy
and a pair of century-old Supreme Court decisions, both joined by
Justice Harlan, that upheld statutes depriving polygamists of the
power to vote.
These precedents may justify Amendment 2, but they cannot support
Justice Scalia's neutrality. Before Romer, there was no Supreme
Court precedent for laws favoring homosexuals over heterosexuals.
Do such laws stand on equal constitutional footing with laws criminalizing
or disfavoring homosexuality, notwithstanding the radical contemporaniety
of the homosexual rights movement? Justice Scalia more than suggests
that the answer to that question is yes.
In his dissent, Justice Scalia takes care to distance himself from
one of the cases he relies upon, a century-old decision upholding
an anti-polygamy statute on the grounds that the statute was "wholesome
and necessary in the founding of a free, self-governing commonwealth,
fit to take rank as one of the co-ordinate States of the Union."
Justice Scalia quotes the decision but adds a disclaimer: "I
would not myself indulge in such official praise for heterosexual
monogamy, because I think it no business of the courts (as opposed
to the political branches) to take sides in this culture war."
One can only interpret Justice Scalia's disclaimer as evidence
of Rieff's maxim that the pretense of neutrality in the Kulturkampf
amounts to taking the anti-cultural side in the fight. It is unlikely
that any of the ratifiers of the original Constitution or the Equal
Protection Clause conceived of heterosexual marriage as anything
other than a sacred institution requiring no explicit constitutional
protection. The modern Kulturkampf is of more recent vintage. Yet
the most prominent originalist on the current Supreme Court is the
first to question whether "official praise for heterosexual
monogamy" is constitutionally suspect.
Justice Scalia's dissent reveals the progress of the Kulturkampf
within legal thinking. On the one surface, he is critical of modern
legal reasoning and the ethics it serves. He heaps scorn on the
majority opinion, for its lack of intellectual rigor, and on the
Association of American Law Schools, for having established that
employers must treat a student's homosexuality with indifference,
but may withhold a job offer due to the applicant's political party
or country club.
On a deeper level, however, Justice Scalia's jurisprudence embraces
the same skepticism toward inherited morality that is shared by
almost all legal academics today. Justice Scalia may be an observant
Catholic, but he has adopted the jurisprudence of Justice Holmes,
an atheist whose radical positivism scandalized Catholic natural-law
advocates earlier this century.
In dissent, Justice Holmes once famously wrote, "If in the
long run the beliefs expressed in proletarian dictatorship are destined
to be accepted by the dominant forces of the community, the only
meaning of free speech is that they should be given their chance
and have their way."5 Fortunately for our nation, the full
implications of this dissent were never tested. Justice Holmes possessed
the luxury of writing at a time when communists were a "small
minority" who posed "no present danger" of overthrowing
the government. Justice Scalia, by contrast, writes with the knowledge
that those whose practices he may privately oppose have more allies
on the Supreme Court than does he.
Unlike the war against communism, the Kulturkampf is largely a
civil war, one in which the fight over constitutional meaning is
a central battleground. The jurisprudential question obscured by
the many battles is whether the words of the Constitution can be
interpreted to sanction assaults on the culture from which the Constitution
sprang.
Justice Scalia's positivism not only prevents him from defending
the culture to which he unofficially swears allegiance, but as the
precedents accumulate on the opposite side of the ledger, Justice
Scalia may find himself forced to take the side of his present-day
opponents and defend their claims with equal vigor. Until the day
before yesterday, he could write that logic and precedent were on
the side of those who thought that homosexuals were not entitled
to protected legal status. After Romer, Justice Scalia will have
difficulty defending restrictions on homosexual marriage, to take
but one example soon to confront the Court.
A truly conservative jurisprudence must acknowledge that the Constitution
was not written with the expectation that judges would maintain
a precarious balance above a raging culture war below. The better
reading of our constitutional heritage is to interpret the Constitution
against the background of commanding truths that informed the drafters
of the document. This was the method of Justice Harlan. It should
become the method for conservative Justices, especially if they
intend today's dissents to become tomorrow's law.
* Joel Friedlander is president of the Delaware Chapter of the
Federalist Society's Lawyers Division. The views expressed in this
article are his own and not necessarily those of the chapter.
1 May 20, 1996, No. 94-1039
2163 U.S. 537 (1896).
3Philip Rieff, Newer Noises of War in the Second Culture Camp:
Notes on Professor Burt's Legal Fictions, 3 Yale J.L. & Human.
315, 326 (199 1).
4478 U.S. 186 (1986).
5Gitlow v. New York, 268 U.S. 652 (1925)
|